“Alice laughed: "There's no use trying," she said; "one can't believe impossible things."
"I daresay you haven't had much practice," said the Queen. "When I was younger, I always did it for half an hour a day. Why, sometimes I've believed as many as six impossible things before breakfast."
Lewis
Carroll, Alice in Wonderland and through the Looking Glass
In
order to justify religious faith as a rational endeavor, I will examine
what we usually mean by belief and knowledge, and to show, by example, the
difference between rational and irrational faith. My motivation for
proceeding from this starting point is to show that the arguments of
evangelical atheists (those published and those posting on web-sites) ignore
their own faith assumption in choosing science (or perhaps more properly the
scientific method) as the only source for justifying belief and gaining
knowledge. From my background of 50 years as a practicing physicist, I
will try to draw examples to show that faith is integral to a scientific
world-view, as well as a religious one.
- BELIEF
"Lord, I believe. Help Thou my unbelief." Mark, 9:24
Let's
talk about belief first. Clearly there is a difference between the
statements "I believe in one God..." (the Credo) and "I believe
it's going to rain tomorrow". An obvious difference is what
one is willing to do or to pay in order to act on one's belief. The
Christian martyrs were willing to suffer and to die for their beliefs;
you might be willing to bet five dollars that it will rain tomorrow, but not
your life, no matter what the weather forecast is.
Accordingly,
there are degrees of belief, which in fact can be quantified using various
techniques in subjective probability and decision theory (see "Probability
and the Art of Judgment" and "Subjective Probability--The Real
Thing" by Richard Jeffrey). To explore these methods in detail would
require a book, not a blog, but those interested can go to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy articles .
Possibly the most famous example of quantifying belief and using outcome
probabilities as a guide to action is Pascal's Wager, in which the argument is
made that belief in God is the prudent choice, given the existence of an
afterlife (even though the probability of that existence might be
infinitesimally small). Objections, most of which are substantial
to Pascal's arguments, have been raised and countered (see Pascal's Wager Revisited--The Pearl of Great Price
and Pascal's Wager--Insurance for Agnostics .) Nevertheless,
it is clear that we don't always act rationally in terms of our
beliefs. We will bet on the lottery, even if the odds--expectation
value for a likely gain--are not in our favor. We will take on
insurance, even if, again, it will in the long run be a losing
proposition. As Pascal himself argued (Pensees, #233), it is
not always easy to believe on the basis of prudence and rationality:
I am so made that I cannot believe. What, then, would you have me do?”
Pascal
replies:
“Endeavor then to convince yourself, not by increase of proofs of God, but by the abatement of your passions. You would like to attain faith and do not know the way; you would like to cure yourself of unbelief, and ask the remedy for it...There are people... who are cured of an ill of which you would be cured. Follow the way by which they began: by acting as if they believed, taking the holy water, having masses said, etc.”
Now
can one “fake it until you make it” as Pascal suggests? Or will the
sacraments be ineffective, because the motive of the recipient is
mercenary? Which of the Catechism dicta are appropriate,
(1131)”The sacraments are efficacious signs of grace....They bear fruit in those who receive them with the required dispositions.”or
(1128) “The sacrament is not wrought by the righteousness of either the celebrant or the recipient, but by the power of God.”
The
second suggests that if one prays for faith, then the “top-down” approach will
work, starting from the head and eventually through to the heart, or, as
Pascal suggests:
“...at each step you take on this road you will see so great certainty of gain, so much nothingness in what you risk, that you will at last recognize that you have wagered for something certain and infinite, for which you have given nothing.”
So
we can see that belief is not an absolute, a two-valued yes or no, but a
quality that is measured on a continuous scale, and that can be implemented by
means that may be other than rational.
The
next segment will deal the bases for belief, knowledge and faith, and, in
particular, what constitutes scientific knowledge.
See
ya....
Duhem
The header picture shows again, that although empirical evidence (e.g. what's happened in the past) should rationally be a basis for belief and thus for action, we don't always follow through--we're all Charlie Browns at times.
No comments:
Post a Comment